Schumacher Lecture 1: Capitalism and the Commons

October 2003, Stockbridge, Massachusetts

Introduction by Susan Witt

The name Peter Barnes has been a household word at the E. F. Schumacher Society since our formation in 1980.  In 1973 Peter organized a conference called “Who Owns the Land?” that both our board President, Robert Swann, and our Chairman, John McClaughry, described as the best conference they ever attended.  When John McClaughry encouraged us to sponsor our first decentralist conference, he said, “You know, I’m really looking for the energy, the vitality, the historic content of that 1973 conference.”  So Peter Barnes and his legacy have been hovering over our heads since the beginning of the Schumacher Society.

Peter Barnes, when he organized that conference, was a reporter for The New Republic.  He was also an activist, working on social and ecological issues.  Following that period in his life he became an entrepreneur, involved with solar energy products, and then in the 1980s he cofounded the Working Assets Long Distance telephone company.  The idea was to bring a social impulse into a capitalist structure.  It is a successful company from which he is now retired.  He is following his original impulse of love and concern for the commons in his book Who Owns the Sky? and now in “The State of the Commons,” a paper you’ll find out on the pamphlet table.

During the last year of his life Bob Swann was having trouble seeing; it was a spatial memory loss, and he could no longer read his favorite books, but he had good friends who would read them to him.  The book he chose to have read to him three times in that year was Peter Barnes’s Who Owns the Sky?  If Bob were here, he would be thrilled to see such a large group gathered on an issue he devoted his life to, a concern for redefinition of our relationship to the land.  He would highly recommend to you our next speaker, Peter Barnes.

I FIRST ENCOUNTERED E. F. Schumacher in 1973, when Small Is Beautiful was published in the United States.  At that time I was a reporter for The New Republic magazine, and a friend told me I had to read this book.  I did, and—as we put it in those days—I was “blown away.”  Never before had I read a book by an economist that was so impassioned, so literary, so unafraid to challenge prevailing orthodoxy.  When I then reviewed Small Is Beautiful for The New Republic, I wrote: “I had never heard of E. F. Schumacher before reading this book.  After reading it I am ready to nominate him for the Nobel Prize in economics.”  I still am.

Schumacher wrote eloquently about many things.  For some people, his most important contributions had to do with scale and appropriate technology.  For me, rereading him thirty years later, what stands out is his focus on permanence.  “From an economic point of view,” he wrote, “the central concept of wisdom is permanence.  Nothing makes economic sense unless its continuance for a long time can be projected without running into absurdities.”

One major problem with capitalism is that the market, as Schumacher noted, “utterly disregards things which cannot be, or have not been, privately appropriated, but are nonetheless an essential precondition of all human activity, such as air, water, the soil, and in fact the whole framework of living nature.”  The result is that we humans are destroying our own nest.  And not only our nest but the nest of all other creatures who share our planet.  The second large problem with capitalism is inequality.  Schumacher didn’t dwell on this, but another of my favorite writers, Tom Paine, did.  I’ll come back to inequality and Tom Paine later.

Today I want to look at these twin problems of capitalism—inequality and the lack of permanence—through a new lens.  That lens is the commons.  Why this particular lens?  Let me back up and say that even before I read Schumacher, I had been struggling to understand the capitalist system in which we live.  First, as a boy crunching numbers for my father’s books on the stock market, then as a student of economics in college, later as a journalist and a political activist, and lastly, for twenty years, as a business person.  My main motive for being a business person was not to make a lot of money but to see how far the boundaries of capitalism could be pushed by working from within.

I think I have a pretty good understanding of capitalism by now—both its virtues and its flaws.  And I should say that I like many aspects of capitalism; I like the freedom, the dynamism, the creativity it unleashes.  I would never, ever, want to do away with the market as the primary engine of productivity.  Yet, while I appreciate the market’s virtues and know the problems it can solve, I also recognize those it cannot solve and those it inexorably makes worse.  In this latter category are the two very big problems I mentioned earlier—tragedies, really, of major proportion: the destruction of age-old natural systems and the exacerbation of inequality among humans.

These are fundamental systemic flaws.  Not something that can be fixed by patches here and there, by stopping this or saving that, by spending more on education or adding a few government regulations.  Such reforms may make us feel better and may even be beneficial, but they do not fundamentally change a system that disregards permanence and increases inequality by its very nature.

Let me be clear about this.  Any economic system whose core mathematical calculus is to maximize short-term profit for a few is bound to create these results.  It is no accident that despite more than a century of non-systemic reforms, the great profit-maximizing, nature-destroying, wealth-concentrating juggernaut that modern capitalism is, marches on.

The primary problem is the economic system itself, and by that I mean not only the market but also everything that surrounds and interacts with the market.  It is the economic system as a whole that must be reprogrammed—“upgraded,” if you will, like a computer operating system.  But how?  What’s wrong with the current operating system?  What’s missing?  As I’ve thought about this question from various perspectives, the answer I have come to is this: the missing piece.  The piece, without which the market will never function properly, is the commons.  It is that part of the whole system I want to draw your attention to today.

In many ways the commons is like the dark matter of the universe.  It’s everywhere, but we don’t see it.  The only economic matter we see is the kind that glistens with dollar signs.  In my mind, the great challenge for the twenty-first century is to make the commons visible, to give it proper reverence, and to translate that reverence into property rights and legal institutions that are on a par with those we currently give to private property.  If this challenge is met, I think we can solve the problems of lack of permanence and of inequality while retaining what is best about capitalism.

What is the Commons?

It is important to distinguish between a commons and the commons.  A commons is specific: the playground down the street, the Housatonic River, the Boston Common.  The commons is an abstract concept similar to the market or the state.  It is the sum of thousands, perhaps millions, of individual commons.  Today I will talk mostly about the commons as a concept representing the sum of many smaller commons.

What, then, is the commons?  There is no simple or obvious answer, so let me wander around a bit before I offer a modern and I hope useful definition.

First of all, the commons consists of stuff we share.  That is to say, whether it is a street or a river or the air or the vast store of human knowledge—none of these belongs to you or me or private corporations.  They are something we share in one way or another.

Second, the commons consists of stuff we inherit.  It is not made up of anything that you or I or some corporation makes.  One can present a very good case that if you make or invent something, it should be your private property, at least for a while.  This is an entirely appropriate way of rewarding people and businesses for value they create and risks they take.  But air and water and ecosystems and DNA and language and legal as well as political institutions are not made by any individual or corporation.  They are gifts we inherit, either from nature or from the collective efforts of millions of humans.

Third, the commons consists of stuff we must pass on to future generations.  Just as we receive the commons as a gift, so too we have a moral obligation to pass this gift on to our children in at least as good condition as we received it.  If we can add to it, improve it, so much the better.  At a minimum we must not degrade it, and we certainly have no right to destroy it.

Fourth, the kinds of things that tend to be commons are not small; they tend to be large, and they tend to be spaces or systems—natural systems or social systems.  Within these spaces and systems there can be private pieces: for example, many pieces of the Internet or of a watershed may be privately owned.  But the Internet and the watershed as whole systems are commons, and we share them.  The systems, if not all the pieces, are parts of the commons.

And fifth, let me dispel two myths that have obstructed clear thinking about the commons for many years.  One is the myth that all commons are inherently self-destructive.  This myth is largely the result of a 1968 essay called “The Tragedy of the Commons” by the late biologist Garrett Hardin.  Hardin assumed that there is basically only one kind of commons: the unfenced pasture or waste dump with no management system, areas to which individuals can add animals and wastes freely and at will with no limitation.   As a result destruction can result.  What Hardin overlooked is that there are many kinds of commons and many ways to manage them. For example, you can put a fence around a pasture or you can put a fence around a waste dump and charge a dumping fee; you can have fishing and hunting limits and sell licenses.  There is no tragedy if a commons is treated properly.

The other myth is that a commons must always be free and open to anyone who wants to use it.  In an uncrowded world, this would be the ideal way to run a commons, but in a crowded world, such as the one we now inhabit, we must not allow unlimited dumping into the air, the water, and the soil.  We must put limits on the uses of many of our commons: on the noises we allow into the shared spaces around us, on hunting and fishing, cutting of trees, posting of billboards.  We can charge tolls for parking on city streets, for using congested highways, and for driving into the center of cities such as London.  All these are legitimate management tools to protect and preserve different kinds of commons.

There are numerous reasons why the commons is so important.  We all know why the market is important: it produces and distributes the vast array of goods and services that characterize our high-consumption society.  What the commons does for all of us is less obvious—in part, I should note, because the commons never advertises!

  1. For most of human existence the commons supplied everyone’s food, water, fuel, and medicines.  People hunted, fished, gathered wild fruits and herbs, collected firewood and building materials, grazed their animals in common pastures, and farmed on common lands. In other words, the commons was the source of basic sustenance.  This is still true today in many parts of the world, and even in the city where I live, San Francisco, there are people who fish in the Bay, not for sport but for food.
  2. The commons is the source of all natural resources and nature’s many replenishing services.  Water, air, DNA, seeds, topsoil, fire, electricity, minerals, wild animals, domesticable animals, edible plants, healing plants, solar energy, wind energy, water power, forests, rivers, ultraviolet protection, climate regulation, biodiversity, and much more.  These are all parts of the commons.
  3. The commons is our ultimate waste sink. It recycles water, oxygen, carbon, and everything else we excrete, exhale, and throw away. It is the place where we store, or try to store, the toxic residues of our modern industrial system.
  4. The commons holds and disseminates humanity’s vast accumulation of science, art, customs, and laws.  It is the seedbed of all human creativity.  As Isaac Newton said, “If I have seen further it is by standing on the shoulders of giants.”  Without the open sharing of ideas, there would be no religion, science, mathematics, philosophy, children’s games, musical instruments, dances, jazz, hip-hop, fashion, sports, democracy, universities, libraries—the list goes on.
  5. The commons is essential to human communication.  We talk to one another with shared symbols and languages that are the living products of many generations.  Most of the spaces we communicate through—the air that carries sound, the visual environment we use for traffic signs and billboards, the vast global web of wires and switches we call the Internet, the electromagnetic waves we use for radio, TV, and cell phones—are parts of the commons.
  6. We use the commons whenever we travel from place to place, whether by land, water, or air.  If we could not use the commons in this way, we would be prisoners in our private homes.
  7. We rely on the commons for our sense of community.  The commons is the village tree, the public square, Main Street, the neighborhood, and the playground.  In addition to families, it’s the glue that holds us together.

Now I’d like to speak about the history of the commons, which is as old as the earth itself.  As I said a moment ago, for most of human existence it was—and for many still is—the source of basic sustenance.  From a conceptual standpoint, the idea of the commons goes back hundreds of years.

The Romans distinguished among three types of property: res privatæ, res publicæ, and res communes.  The first consisted of things capable of being possessed by an individual or family, the second of things built and set aside for public use by the state, such as public buildings and roads, and the third of natural things used by all, such as air, water, and wild animals.  This was codified in the Institutes of Justinian, the grand summation of Roman law, which said: “By the law of nature these things are common to mankind—the air, running water, the sea, and consequently the shore of the sea.”

In the United Kingdom during the Middle Ages, the commons were shared lands used by villagers for foraging, hunting, planting crops, and harvesting wood.  In 1215 the Magna Carta established forests and fisheries as res communes, resources available to all.

In America, four early states—Massachusetts, Pennsylvania, Virginia, and Kentucky—called themselves “commonwealths.”  Several states declared in their constitutions that natural resources belong to the people and that the government acts as the people’s trustee.  The Pennsylvania Constitution still contains the words: “Pennsylvania’s public natural resources are the common property of all the people, including generations yet to come. As trustee of these resources, the Commonwealth shall conserve and maintain them for the benefit of all the people.”

This, in a nutshell, is the good side of the history of the commons.  Unfortunately, there is a bad side, a tragic side, as well.  That is the long history of enclosure of the commons, which began in eighteenth-century England and continues to this day, in America and almost everywhere in the world.  As Andrew Kimbrell said in his Schumacher Lecture a few years ago: “It’s no longer just the enclosure of the lands: it’s the enclosure of our genes, it’s the enclosure of the seas; it’s the corporate enclosure of virtually the entire living commons.”

Enclosure is an old-fashioned word for privatization.  At first it meant privatization by the landed gentry; today it means privatization by corporations.  Either way, it means that what once belonged to many now belongs to a few. Enclosure is usually justified in the name of “efficiency.”  And sometimes it does result in efficiency gains.  But what also results from enclosure is the impoverishment of those who lose access to the commons and the enrichment of those who take title to it. In other words, enclosure widens the gap between those with income-producing property and those without .

At this point, having wandered around a little, I am ready to offer a modern definition of the commons.  I say “modern” because I want to erase from our minds the antiquated notion of the commons as a pasture or a plot of land.  The most useful way to understand the commons today is as the sum of all we inherit together and must pass on, undiminished and more or less equally, to our heirs.  (Here I include non-human as well as human heirs.)  Another way of saying this is that the commons consists of that which nobody owns or which we all own together—in contrast to the market, which consists of that which we own privately.

Either way, the economy as a whole system is divided between the market and the commons.  Within the market part of the system is what we manage mostly for the short-term monetary gain of a property-owning class; within the commons part of the system is what we manage—or should manage, because we don’t at the moment—for the long-term enhancement of all living beings.

Economists, politicians, and the media have tended to focus almost exclusively on the market side of the economy, even though the commons is just as important.  (In fact, the commons happens to be worth more, even in crude dollar terms, than the market, but I don’t want to get into bean-counting here.)  Whatever their relative value, the commons precedes the market, and is the source of most that enters the market and the sink for all that leaves it.  To put this in visual terms, we might say that the commons surrounds the market. Or, more dynamically, that the commons is the pond in which the fish of private property swim.

I like the fish-in-the-pond image for a couple of reasons.  First, it conveys the notion that both the market and the commons are living systems, with constantly moving and interacting parts.  The pond is a soup of water, air, light, heat, currents, nutrients, and life forms; the fish are active, competitive creatures constantly on the move, taking what they need from the pond, growing, excreting, reproducing, and dying.  This is pretty much how corporations operate.  Second, the pond-and-fish image points to a rather remarkable aspect of corporations.  Unlike real fish or any other life form, the corporation has no optimum or maximum size.  It can grow, or presumes it can grow, ad infinitum, without damaging the pond. Of course, if we think about it, this is an impossibility.

In any case, the economic system as a whole has these two distinct sectors, the commons and the market.  They have different rules and different guiding principles, and the boundaries between these sectors shift over time.  For the past three hundred years this shift has been in one direction only: the market has steadily expanded into the commons.

What I am proposing is that from this moment forward we reverse that direction.  I believe this is not only absolutely necessary but eminently doable—if we put our minds to it. In the rest of my lecture I would like to show how.  First, though, I need to say a bit more about the market and the state.

The Market and The State

In the minds of most economists the market floats in an unbounded universe.  It takes resources from this universe, transforms them into products that can be profitably sold, and returns all wastes into unlimited sinks.  If any particular resource runs out, the market can—thanks to human ingenuity—replace it with another.  Because both sinks and resources, with substitutions, are unlimited, this game can go on forever.  But as Schumacher and many others have pointed out, this view is a delusion.  It is a delusion not so much because we will run out of resources but because we will run out of sinks.  This exhaustion of sinks is most imminent, somewhat surprisingly, in the sky.  In the 1970s Schumacher warned that we would shortly run out of oil; in fact, there is still a fair amount of oil left in the ground, and a great deal of gas and coal as well.  But long before we run out of fossil fuels, we are going to use up the atmosphere’s capacity to safely absorb the wastes produced by burning them.

This is not the place to go into the details of climate change.  If you are interested, you can read my book Who Owns The Sky?  My point here is that the atmosphere is not infinite.  It is a scarce, and hence valuable, economic resource.  It is also a commons that is being used by polluters for free, and as a result it’s being turned into a sewer.  To put this into Schumacher’s words, because the market “utterly disregards” the air, we are well on our way to melting the polar icecaps, redirecting the Gulf Stream, and radically altering life on earth.  This has to do with the problem of impermanence that the market, by itself, cannot solve.

Let me now offer another way of thinking about the market.  I’m sure many of you have seen the classic Disney movie “Fantasia.”  In it there’s a wonderful segment starring Mickey Mouse as the Sorcerer’s Apprentice.  Mickey is charged with cleaning up the workshop; he thinks he can make his job easier by having the broom carry a bucket of water for him. With a wave of his arms he gleefully directs the broom, which then goes out of control.  In a panic Mickey takes an ax and chops the broom into many pieces, but each piece turns into a new broom carrying a new bucket, and soon the entire workshop is engulfed by a raging flood.  Only when the wise old Sorcerer returns is the watery chaos brought under control.

In many ways the market is like those out-of-control brooms.  It is populated by an army of corporations that are programmed, like robots, to maximize short-term profit for the few.  No matter how you shout at them or chop them up, they keep doing what they are programmed to do.  The Sorcerer who knows how to stop them is nowhere to be found.

Of course, corporations do create useful products and jobs.  But the robotic calculus that drives them compels them to pay as little as possible for the resources they use and to shift as many costs as possible to others—be it workers, tax-payers, future generations, or nature.  This happens daily, automatically, and on a massive scale, with nobody able to stop it.

Now, the fact that corporations act like profit-maximizing robots, shifting as many costs as possible to others, is not a shocking revelation.  It has been pointed out repeatedly for at least one hundred years.  What is new is that the accumulation of these externalized costs has reached the point where the biological integrity of our planet is in grave danger.  I don’t need to describe the indicators—extinction of species, alteration of the climate, accumulation of toxic chemicals, degradation of forests, oceans, aquifers and wetlands, etc.—because you know them well. My point is that this cannot go on much longer.  The problem we need to solve—and quickly—is how to stop, and indeed reverse, this systematic carnage.

It is helpful to look at this problem through the lens of the commons.  I’ve talked about enclosure and how for three hundred years the market has been privatizing everything it can get its hands on.  And I’ve talked about externalization and how for roughly the same period of time the market has been dumping wastes and unpaid costs into the commons.  In effect, what has been going on is a relentless, two-pronged assault by the market on the commons.  With one hand the market takes good stuff from the commons; with the other hand it dumps bad stuff into the commons.  If someone were keeping a balance sheet of our common wealth, it would not look good.

Part of the problem is that no one is keeping such a balance sheet, which is quite odd, given that double-entry bookkeeping was invented in the sixteenth century.  Every economist and business person knows that one person’s income is another person’s expense and that liabilities for the most part offset assets.  Yet when it comes to keeping double-entry books for the market and the commons as a whole, we simply don’t do that.

A bigger part of the problem is that the contest between the market and the commons has not been an even one.  It’s been like a World Series between the New York Yankees and the Portland Sea Dogs.  One side has all the money, the top hitters, and the best pitchers; it also, I might add, pays the umpires.  Sports metaphors aside, it is extremely important to understand why the market is so much stronger than the commons.  There are multiple reasons, to be sure, but there are two that I would like to highlight today.  One has to do with law—or, more precisely, with property rights; the second has to do with institutions.

Divine Right

Let’s look first at property rights.  Marjorie Kelly has written a brilliant book called The Divine Right of Capital.  By “divine” she doesn’t mean God-given, although there are indeed some apologists for capitalism who attribute the current design of our economy to the Almighty.  What she means is that under the current laws of our land, the rights of capital trump everything else.  The rights of employees, the rights of communities, the rights of nature, and the rights of future generations are all subordinate to the right of capital to maximize short-term profit for the few.

This primacy of capital is embedded not only in state and federal law but also in international treaties such as the General Agreement on Tariffs and Trade (GATT) and the North America Free Trade Agreement (NAFTA).  Thus, a California company, Sun Belt Water, wanted to export water from Canada in supertankers and sell it to southern Californians.  Canada said no, so the company sued Canada for billions of dollars in damages, claiming that under NAFTA its right to make a profit trumped Canada’s right to protect its natural resources.

Now, the question of who gets the divine right in any society is always an interesting one.  Because I have a fifteen-year-old son who is learning to drive, I read the California Drivers’ Manual the other day and came across the following rule: “At an intersection, yield to the car which arrives first or to the car on your right if it reaches the intersection at the same time you do.”  Why does the car on the right trump the car on the left?  It’s unclear.  Quite possibly the rule is entirely arbitrary, but someone has to have the right of way or cars will collide.  The same is true for boats at sea and for moving objects in any complex system.  Someone has to be “king of the road.”

So too in a market economy.  When two property rights come to the same intersection, one has to trump the other. Either capital can trump labor, or labor can trump capital.  Either my right to pollute trumps your right not to be polluted, or vice versa.  One of the conflicting property rights, you might say, has to be the divine right.  But which one? Invariably, those who hold the divine right in any era say there is no choice: they are the only conceivable holders of this right.  Kings said it three hundred years ago; capital owners say it today.  Kings hired priests to lend moral credence to their claims whereas capital owners now hire economists to lend “scientific” credence to their claims.  The truth is, though, that we do have a choice.  Society chooses the divine-right holder, and its choice can change over time.

Bear in mind that even if we aren’t talking literally about divinity, we are talking about reverence.  Reverence doesn’t come from “up there”; it comes from “in here.”  Today, despite all our speechifying about family values, God, and nature, we in the West revere capital above all.  That is why we give it trumping rights in our economy—indeed, that is why we call our economic system “capitalism.”  If we were to revere the commons as fervently as we currently revere capital, our divine right would shift.

To bring our discussion back to the problems of impermanence and inequality: it seems to me that if anything is divine, it ought to be those things we inherit together and should pass on, undiminished and more or less equally, to future generations. Permanence should trump impermanence.  Broad benefit should trump narrow benefit. The commons should trump capital.

From an historical perspective the explosion of the market over the past three hundred years has been a logical response to the problem of scarce goods and services; it makes perfect sense that, during this time, capital held the divine right so that it could efficiently flood the world with goods and services.  But now we humans, as the dominant imperial species, are approaching what Schumacher called “the tolerance limits of nature.”  Today our problem, at least in the West, is not the scarcity of goods and services; it’s the scarcity of nature and of equity, time, and quiet.  Therefore, it makes historic sense that the divine right in modern, postindustrial economies should shift to the commons.

Of course, this is easier said than done. I can think of only one American law—the Endangered Species Act—that gives precedence to permanence over transience, to the commons over capital.  The Endangered Species Act says that the right of a species to survive trumps the right of capital to short-term profit. The trouble is that the law comes into play only in extremis, when a species has been so decimated that it is on the brink of extinction.  The more general situation is not just that capital trumps the commons but that the commons has no rights at all.  Protections for private property are enshrined in our Constitution, whereas the notion that there even is such a thing as the commons is still in its infancy.

I want to add two more thoughts about legal rights here.  The first is that there is a difference between human rights and property rights.  Human rights include the rights to life, liberty, speech, and so on; property rights involve the power to own, control, and sell things, to limit other people’s use of them, and to charge prices for using them.  There may also be a third class, that of nonhuman rights, such as those proposed by Thomas Berry this morning.  I want to be clear that what I’m talking about today is property rights, recognizing that these property rights have significant implications for human and nonhuman rights.

The other point I want to make about property rights involves one of the more original economists of the twentieth century, Ronald Coase.  Coase worked with Milton Friedman at the University of Chicago and is considered a conservative.  A Nobel Prize winner, he is most recognized for his theorem that pollution can be reduced more efficiently through property rights than through government regulation.

One aspect of Coase’s argument is that if pollutees are given the right not to be polluted, they can bargain in the market with polluters, and the end results will be that (a) polluters will pay pollutees a price based on how much pollution the pollutees are willing to accept as well as how badly the polluters want to pollute, and (b) there will consequently be less pollution.  He also argued that the property-rights approach would work just as well if polluters are given the right to pollute and pollutees pay them not to pollute.  He was strangely indifferent to the question of who should get the initial property rights and who should pay whom.

Coase’s theorem became the basis for so-called “cap-and-trade” programs such as the trading of sulfur dioxide initiated in the 1990s to reduce acid rain.  These programs, which are now fairly popular as ways of reducing pollution, are generally supported by business because they allow polluters to figure out the cheapest ways to reduce pollution.  Unfortunately, they have thus far been set up with the initial property rights given free to polluters.  The economic result is that billions of dollars have been paid by pollutees to polluters.

How does this work? Well, economists have a concept called “scarcity rent.”  Scarcity rent is like a bonus that owners of something in high demand collect from other people just because of scarcity.  The Mona Lisa, for example, has a high scarcity rent; because there is only one, it is in great demand.  In general, the scarcer things are—such as buildable land, Barry Bonds home-run balls, and New York taxi medallions—the higher the bonus for scarcity.  As OPEC or any other cartel knows, when you restrict supply you can raise prices and profits, sometimes by huge amounts.

What happens when we set up a cap-and-trade system and give the initial property rights to polluters?  First of all, we reduce pollution, which is good. Secondly, we raise the price of polluting, currently at zero.  This is also good.  And thirdly, we raise the prices of all goods and services now made with expensive polluting processes.  This too is appropriate. But think about who gets to keep the extra money we pay for these goods.  If polluters are given scarce pollution rights for free, then we, the ultimate consumers and pollutees, end up paying scarcity rent to them forever. Imagine that!  Because a corporation polluted in the past, it gets free money forever.  Over the long term, this would be an enormous transfer of wealth to shareholders of historically polluting corporations.  I’ll come back to this question of who gets initial property rights—polluters or pollutees—in a minute.

The other reason the commons is much weaker than the market, in addition to the supremacy of capital’s rights, is institutional imbalance.  As I noted earlier, the market is populated by aggressive, profit-maximizing robots armed with property rights, money, lawyers, and lobbyists. The commons, by contrast, is institutionally threadbare.

There is no institution that “owns” the sky or the Housatonic River watershed and that can say to a corporation: “Stop!  This is common property.  You can’t trespass here for free.”  There are just a handful of institutions whose mission is to preserve common assets for the future and who have the property rights needed to carry out that mission.  This institutional imbalance means that the commons is essentially defenseless against the ceaseless aggression of the market.

This brings us to the subject of the role of the state in defending the commons.  The first point we need to be clear about is that the state is not the commons.  The state is the state and the commons is the commons.  Americans often get confused about this because so much land in our country is state-owned.  In theory these public lands are part of the commons, but at best they are a small part, and the mere fact that the state owns them in no way guarantees that they will be managed as the commons should be managed.  Quite the contrary, the state more often than not has been a co-conspirator with private industry in managing public lands for short-term profit rather than long-term preservation.  The U. S. Forest Service, for example, has spent billions of tax dollars building logging roads in national forests; it then sells logging rights to private companies for less than private landowners do.  Similarly, grazing and mineral rights on federal lands are sold for a song. And the public air-waves that carry radio and TV signals are given free to giant media conglomerates owned by Disney, General Electric, and Rupert Murdoch.

There is a legal principle called the Public Trust Doctrine that I should mention here.  This principle arose from common law, though it is embodied in several state constitutions, such as Pennsylvania’s.  The Public Trust Doctrine holds that natural resources belong to the people rather than to the state and that it is the state’s responsibility to act as trustee of these resources for present and future generations.  If the state does not act as a trustee should, the people have the right to hire another trustee.  The principle of trusteeship is very important, and I’ll come back to it shortly.  Suffice it to say here that a private trustee who gives away entrusted assets would be sued, fired, and probably sent to jail.  But this rarely happens when the state is trustee.

As for the Public Trust Doctrine itself, the difficulty is similar to the difficulty with the Endangered Species Act: it comes into play only in extremis, after a state has failed to protect a resource.  In such cases, citizens can sue the state and a court can order the state to remedy its breach of the public trust.  But it costs millions of dollars to bring such a suit, and needless to say, it is seldom done.  For this reason, despite its sound philosophy, the Public Trust Doctrine is an inadequate tool for defending the commons against the everyday assaults of the market.  Of course, if the state were acting as a proper trustee of the commons in the first place, lawsuits under the Public Trust Doctrine would be unnecessary.  Which brings us to three critical questions:

  1. What is the role of a commons trustee?
  2. Why has the state not been a good commons trustee?
  3. If the state isn’t a good commons trustee, who can be?

The Role of Trusts

When we think of capitalist institutions, the one that immediately comes to mind is the corporation.  But there is another institution that is as old and as firmly established as the corporation, and that is the trust.

The essence of a trust is a fiduciary relationship, i.e., one that is based on the beneficiary’s confidence in the trustee.  A trustee holds and manages property for another person or for many other people.  A simple example is a trust established by a grandmother so that her grandchildren will have money to go to college.  She then appoints a trustee, a bank for example, which by law has a fiduciary responsibility to manage the assets on behalf of the beneficiaries and to assure that the trust’s purpose is achieved.  Other trusts include pension funds, charitable foundations, and university endowments.

The rules of trust management, which are defined by state statutes and by centuries of case law, include the following:

  • Managers must act with undivided loyalty to beneficiaries.  If a manager fails this obligation, s/he can be removed and penalized.
  • In most cases, managers must preserve the principal.  It is acceptable to spend incomebut it is not acceptable to invade the corpus.
  • If the beneficiaries of a trust span many generations, the trustee may not favor one generation over another.
  • Managers must assure transparency.  Information about money flows must be readily available to beneficiaries.

These rules are enforceable by the courts.  The basic mechanism is that an aggrieved beneficiary can bring suit against a trustee, and the trustee must then prove that s/he acted prudently to carry out the mandate of the trust.  This is in contrast to the state: the government can give away whatever it wants with impunity.  There is no legal recourse, except on rare occasions; the politicians have a free hand.

If we were to design an institution to protect pieces of the commons, we couldn’t do much better than a trust.  The goal of commons management, after all, is to preserve assets and deliver benefits to broad classes of beneficiaries.  That is what trusts accomplish.

What, then, can we say about the state’s capacity to serve as a commons trustee?  In theory, the state represents all citizens equally and should be able to protect our common assets.  But in reality, the track record of the state as trustee of the commons has been far from exemplary.  There are at least five reasons for this:

  1. The elected officials who run the state do not have a long-term perspective.  Just as corporate leaders are focused on the next quarterly statement, political leaders are focused on the next election.  They like to please constituents here and now, not worry about future generations.
  2. Elected officials, alas, need money to get re-elected.  It is tempting to trade common assets for private campaign contributions.
  3. Elected officials are not accountable to beneficiaries in the same way private trustees are.  They can give assets away with virtual impunity whereas private trustees, because of their fiduciary responsibility, cannot.
  4. The state and its leaders have many other things to do besides manage common assets.  It’s easy for this task to get neglected.
  5. The state’s finances are huge and complex.  All sorts of funds are commingled.  It’s extremely difficult for the public to track money from common assets or to ascertain whether these assets are being well managed.

Many of my liberal friends get nervous when I make these arguments.  They think I’m aiding and abetting those conservatives who believe the state is always incompetent and the market is always right.  So let me be clear that this is not what I’m saying.  At heart I am an old New Deal liberal.  I believe in limiting corporate power and in achieving a fairer distribution of income and property, but I am a pragmatist when it comes to the means to achieve these ends.  I think the state is good at some things and not good at others.

When it is a matter of defending the commons, the state does have a critical role to play.  That role is not to own and manage the commons directly but to assign common property rights, to nurture the commons with as much vigor as it nurtures the market, and to maintain a healthy balance between the commons and the market.  The problem today is that the state has abandoned this balancing role and has become a single-minded champion of the market.  This is what we must change.

Rebuilding the Commons

As I see it, the great task of the twenty-first century is to build a new and vital common sector that can resist enclosure and externalization by the market, protect the planet, and share the fruits of our common inheritances more equitably than is now the case.

Just as the market is populated by profit-maximizing corporations, so too the common sector needs to be populated by commons-preserving trusts.  These trusts should be endowed with property rights that are equal to those of corporations.  Their beneficiaries should be all citizens equally, as well as future generations and, at times, the larger biotic community.  Their trustees and managers should be legally accountable to these beneficiaries, and their finances should be completely transparent.

There are many models for such trusts, including Community Land Trusts, which were pioneered by Bob Swann, the founder of the Schumacher Society, and Susan Witt, its executive director.  But before I turn to these models, I need to lay out a few general principles for commons management.

Commons managers must, first and foremost, protect shared assets for the long term.  They must also assure that the benefits flowing from the assets are widely shared.  Beyond these basic principles, specific rules for commons management will vary from one commons to another.  Broadly speaking, they depend on the level of use society wishes to allow or encourage.  And here there are three distinct categories, roughly comparable to situations where we want either no parking, free parking, or paid parking.

If we want a commons to be off limits to all but the most noninvasive use—a wilderness area, for example—the guiding rule is, “No parking” or “No trespassing.” This is quite straightforward.

If a commons has no physical limits on use, as with the Internet or the cultural commons, the guiding rule is, “Free parking” or “The more the merrier.”  Use should be as free as possible, and management’s main job should be to minimize private toll booths.  This too is relatively straightforward, at least conceptually if not politically.

The third category is the most complex and also the most prevalent.  This is the category of commons that can be used up to a point but not infinitely.  Fisheries, rivers, aquifers, forests, the atmosphere, congested highways, and crowded streets are examples.  Management’s job is to encourage efficient use and prevent overuse.  In economic terms its challenge is to live from income without diminishing capital.

Interestingly, there’s an old common-law principle that is relevant here.  Called the “riparian principle,” it used to apply to rivers and streams in England and early colonial America.  The riparian principle says that water can be used, but not owned, by those adjacent to it, so long as the users don’t diminish the resource for others.  In other words, you can take from the commons as long as you don’t deplete or pollute it.

Unfortunately, the riparian principle was displaced in America by the “prior appropriation” rule—that is, perpetual property rights belong to whoever takes water first, and there is no limit to what an appropriator can take.  With this kind of property regime, it’s no surprise that America is the most profligate water-using nation in the world by far.

In managing commons where some use is permissible but unlimited use is not, it’s often desirable to set a limit on total use and charge users a fee.  Such limits and prices assure preservation, let markets sort out competing uses, and generate revenue for many potentially good purposes.  It is crucial that a trust representing the commons, not a private polluter, collect the scarcity rent resulting from setting usage limits.

Setting usage limits can be controversial.  If the physical threshold is uncertain, as it usually is, a critical question arises: “Which side should we err on?”  Under the precautionary principle, if the potential harm from overuse is substantial (for example, the polar icecaps might melt), the usage limit should be set with safety as the primary guide.  As lawyer and ethicist Carolyn Raffensperger has stated, “The precautionary principle’s fundamental idea is that we prevent problems rather than clean them up afterward.”

The process of protecting and sustaining a commons involves several steps.  The commons must first be identified, then given legal standing and an institutional infrastructure.  In some cases, usage limitations and new kinds of property rights may be necessary.  It may also be necessary to appoint trustees and acquire pre-existing property rights.

Once a commons is identified, given property rights, and provided with a proper management regime, markets can come into play.  Profit-maximizing corporations, which in the past could freely take from or dump into the commons, will now have to deal with property managers, who can limit their use and make corporations pay for previously externalized costs.

There is one last principle I should mention, and that is the “polluter pays” principle.  This principle has been endorsed by virtually every economist in the world, and the reason for it should be obvious.  It would make a huge difference if this principle were actually built into the economy’s operating system.  The costs of burning fossil fuels, bleaching with chlorine, spraying with pesticides, long-distance transport, and many other commons-diminishing processes would instantly rise, thereby making clean energy, recycling, local organic food production, and other commons-sustaining processes immediately more competitive.

Yes, prices for many things we buy would also rise, but if the money that polluters pay is recycled back to commons owners, which means to all of us, consumers would on average not be penalized.  What’s more, if the dividends are equal, consumers who switch to less polluting products will come out ahead—that is, their dividends will exceed what they pay in higher prices.  By contrast, those who use the most polluting products (and consequently make the most use of scarce common sinks) will pay for that privilege—that is, their higher costs will exceed their dividends.  In short, total pollution will decrease, the right kind of individual behavior will be rewarded, and money will flow from overusers of the commons to underusers (which usually translates into “from rich to poor”).  All this through just a slight tweaking of property rights.  No new taxes or government bureaucracy required.

Real-World Models

It’s time to shift now from what has been a fairly abstract argument to concrete examples.  Many of these are mentioned in the report I co-authored, The State of the Commons 2003/04.  These models are examples of existing institutions—trusts in one form or another—that preserve and manage property on behalf of broad classes of beneficiaries.

State land trusts have been around since 1787, when Congress required western territories to set aside land for “common schools.”  Today over 150 million acres are held in trust by states.  Much of this land is leased for timber, grazing, or oil production, with revenues going to public schools.

The Texas Permanent School Fund owns submerged lands along the Gulf coast.  Proceeds from offshore oil and gas leases launched the Fund in 1954.  Earnings from investments go to local schools.

The Alaska Permanent Fund, launched in the 1970s, is like a communal savings account for all Alaskans.  Initial capital came from oil leases on state land and was put into a trust for the benefit of the citizens of Alaska.  Today a $27 billion diversified portfolio pays a yearly dividend to every Alaskan man, woman, and child equally.  Last year’s dividend was $1,540.

The Marin Agricultural Land Trust buys conservation easements from farmers through the use of private and public funds. Farmers continue to own and operate their farms, but they can’t develop the land because the Trust owns the development rights in perpetuity.  Trust-owned easements preserve the shared landscape and the farm economy.

The Pacific Forest Trust buys conservation easements from private forest owners.  The owners can continue to harvest trees sustainably, but they cannot overcut, and development is not permitted.

The Oregon Water Trust acquires previously allocated water rights and uses them to augment the flow of rivers and streams.

The Edwards Aquifer Authority, which manages the aquifer from which San Antonio, Texas, gets its water, limits withdrawals of underground water and sells tradable withdrawal permits.

The Music Performance Trust Fund was formed in 1948 by the recording industry and the musicians’ union.  A small percentage of record sales goes into a fund that pays for free concerts in schools, parks, and hospitals. Sales of corporate products thus support living culture.

The last model I want to mention doesn’t exist yet, but I fervently hope it comes into being during my lifetime. It is the Sky Trust that I describe in my book, Who Owns The Sky?  The Sky Trust, which is based on the premise that the sky belongs to everyone and must be held in trust for future generations, provides an example of how to take a huge commons, the atmosphere, and manage it from the standpoint of preservation and equity.  It requires polluters to purchase emission permits from a trust representing all citizens.  The trust’s income can be used for public purposes and/or be rebated to citizens through equal dividends, in the manner of the Alaska Permanent Fund.

A study by the Congressional Budget Office found that, of all cap-and-trade systems that might be used to reduce carbon emissions, the Sky Trust would be the easiest to implement, would have the most positive effect on household incomes, and would result in the lowest overall cost to society.

A key point here involves the assignment of initial pollution rights.  This is not just an abstract philosophical question. Because carbon is so pervasive in our economy, literally trillions of dollars are at stake, and the choice must be made whether this money should flow from pollutees to polluters or vice-versa.  It’s a case where “divine right” is worth a great deal of money.

Some of the Sky Trust’s principles are embodied in the McCain-Lieberman bill, called the Climate Stewardship Act, which is coming to a vote next week.  Our President will surely veto the bill if it should pass, but I consider its reaching the Senate floor a significant step toward a rational and equitable climate policy.

I mention these models for two reasons: first, to show that it’s possible to design modern institutions that can preserve and share a valuable commons and, second, to paint a picture of what the twenty-first century could look like.

In the twenty-first century I envision, there would be a large common sector populated by thousands of trusts like those I have mentioned.  The trusts would be as powerful as corporations are today.  They would act as protectors for various commons or, to put it slightly differently, as proxies for externalities that markets currently ignore.  They would have property rights, management, money, and beneficiaries—in short, as much power as the corporations that now populate the market.

The primary engine of productivity would still be profit-maximizing corporations and the market, but this engine would now be tempered by automatic balancing mechanisms, like the governors in James Watt’s steam engines, so that they couldn’t run rampant the way they do now.  There would also be a kind of common property that disperses income equally, as well as private property that disperses income unequally.

The key features of the two types of property appear in the table below.

Private Common
Transferable: Yes No
Universal Birthright: No Yes
Expires at Death: No Yes
Beneficial Ownership: 1 dollar, 1 share 1 person, 1 share
Voting Rights: 1 dollar, 1 vote 1 person, 1 vote
Future generations: No stake Legal stake
Nonhumans: No stake Legal stake
#1 management goal: Maximize short-term profit Preserve assets
Basic management entity: Corporation Trust
Main income source: Corporate profits Commons rents & fees
Pays Dividends: Yes Yes (sometimes)

 

The multiple benefits of this enlargement of property rights would consist of great advances in permanence, in democracy, in popular as opposed to corporate culture, and in economic equality.

The state’s main job in all this is to redraw the boundaries between the commons and the market—to create new common-property rights, shift the divine right from private property to common property, and make it nearly as routine to form and empower commons-preserving trusts as it is to form and empower profit-maximizing corporations. In addition, some of the new commons trusts might be quasi-public, like the Social Security Trust Fund and the Alaska Permanent Fund, to which elected officials appoint some or all of the trustees.

Inequality

Finally, I’d like to talk about Tom Paine and the problem of inequality.

The perpetuation of inequality is built into the current design of capitalism.  Because of the skewed distribution of private wealth, a small self-perpetuating minority receives a disproportionate share of America’s non-labor income.  If the inheritance tax is completely repealed, as George Bush and most Republicans want, we will truly have recreated a permanent aristocracy of wealth, one of the feudal privileges the American Revolution sought to end.

Tom Paine was an amazing man who lived an amazing life.  He was born in England when the commons was being enclosed, came to America and participated in the Revolution here, then moved to France in time to join the Revolution there.

In one of his greatest essays, “Agrarian Justice,” written in 1790, he argued that because enclosure of the commons had separated so many people from their primary source of sustenance, it was necessary to create a functional equivalent of the commons in the form of a National Fund.  Here is how he put it:

There are two kinds of property.  Firstly, natural property, or that which comes to us from the Creator of the universe—such as the earth, air, water.  Secondly, artificial or acquired property—the invention of men.”

In the latter, equality is impossible; for to distribute it equally, it would be necessary that all should have contributed in the same proportion, which can never be the case . . . . Equality of natural property is different.  Every individual in the world is born with legitimate claims on this property, or its equivalent. [emphasis added].

Enclosure of the commons, he went on, was necessary to improve the efficiency of cultivation, but “[t]he landed monopoly that began with [enclosure] has produced the greatest evil.  It has dispossessed more than half the inhabitants of every nation of their natural inheritance, without providing for them, as ought to have been done, an indemnification for that loss, and has thereby created a species of poverty and wretchedness that did not exist before.”

The remedy he proposed was a fund remarkably similar to the Alaska Permanent Fund, except that it was financed not with oil revenue but with ground rents paid by landowners.  Out of this fund there would be paid to every person reaching twenty-one years of age the sum of fifteen pounds sterling (the equivalent of several thousand dollars today) “as a compensation in part, for the loss of his or her natural inheritance.”  An additional sum of ten pounds per year would be paid to every person over age fifty, an idea that foreshadowed Social Security.

This essay, written 213 years ago, could not be more timely today.  Surely from our vast common inheritance—not just the land but the atmosphere, the broadcast spectrum, our mineral resources, our threatened habitats and water supplies—enough rent can be collected to pay every American over twenty-one a modest annual dividend and every person reaching twenty-one a small start-up inheritance. And remember what I said earlier about scarcity rent.  The more we restrict use of the commons, the more dividends we can pay, so there is a double benefit .

If this sounds dangerously communistic, consider the familiar board game Monopolythe capitalist game par excellence, with players buying and selling property and trying to build monopolies.  But Monopoly has two rules that make it very different from capitalism as we know it today.  First, all players receive an equal amount of start-up capital.  Nobody starts off either penniless or inheriting Boardwalk or Park Place.  And second, all players receive an equal dividend every time they complete a trip around the board.  Or consider professional sports—the profit-seeking leagues of baseball, football, and basketball.  Each has a set of rules designed to shift money from the richest teams to the poorest and to give the losing teams first crack at the best new players.  These businesses have learned that too much inequality hurts everyone.  The rules of Monopoly and professional sports in no way inhibit the vigor of the market.  Indeed, they make the market stronger by making it fairer and more competitive.

In a post-modern, over-productive economy like America’s, there is absolutely no reason why every baby should not be a trust-fund baby.  Commons-funded inheritances and commons-funded dividends would strengthen our market economy.  In addition, they would correct the two systemic flaws I spoke of at the beginning.  On the one hand, by limiting commons usage, they would diminish pollution and the destruction of nature.  On the other hand, by distributing common-property income to everyone, they would partially offset the maldistribution of private-property income.  The commons would again be a source of sustenance for all, as it was in pre-enclosure days.

Now, if there are any economists in the audience, I’d like to engage you in a thought experiment.  I want you to think about incentives.  Right now there is a huge incentive to pollute because (a) it’s free to do so, and (b) no one profits if you reduce pollution.  But imagine a system in which pollution sinks are commonly owned through trusts.  These trusts sell a finite number of pollution permits for whatever the market will bear.  And every American receives a dividend from these trusts—one person, one share.  The trustees have the power to decide how many permits to sell. Leaving aside all ecological and legal issues such as the trustees’ fiduciary responsibility to future beneficiaries, my economic question is twofold: Under what circumstances should the trustees sell more permits and under what circumstances should the trustees sell fewer permits?

Just so no one feels left out, here’s another thought experiment for anyone with a little business sense: Imagine that all the critical ecosystems in the world—the oceans, the atmosphere, forests, rivers, watersheds, and so on—are owned by one large holding company called Gaia, Inc., which itself is owned by shareholders on a one person, one share basis. Each ecosystem is managed by a separate company, but all are coordinated by the global holding company.  Each ecosystem manager has the legal right to charge scarcity rent for limited human or corporate use of that ecosystem.  The business question is: If Gaia, Inc., wants to maximize dividends to its shareholders, what strategy should it pursue? (Hint: Think of Gaia, Inc., as a cartel like OPEC whose asset isn’t oil but vital ecosystems.)

It’s important to be clear about what I am not suggesting.  I’m not suggesting that we abolish the market or change its fundamental calculus.  Quite the contrary, I strongly believe we need a sector of the economy that is driven by short-term profit maximization for the few.  We need it for productivity, for creativity, for vitality, and for freedom.  What I am saying is that we should not confuse the calculus of the market with the calculus of our entire society.  As a society we have values that differ from those embodied in the market; therefore, the calculus of the market needs to be balanced by other calculi, other property rights and boundaries.  Limits of nature need to be respected, as do the interests of future generations, those without private property, and nonhuman species.  Within this framework—and, I would argue,only within this framework—the market can flourish indefinitely.

It’s important to note that under this sort of economic operating system, the rules of the market will still be as they are today.  CEOs will not have to change their consciousness; businesses will not have to learn new tricks.  They will still be driven by profit maximization.  The bottom line will still be the bottom line.  The big difference from a business point of view is that costs which are routinely externalized today will, instead, be routinely internalized.  Nature and future generations will be represented in real-time transactions, and money from these transactions will flow to a broad set of “owners,” whose added purchasing power will spur economic activity.

It will be claimed that this new operating system in which the market and the commons are on a roughly equal footing will reduce Gross Domestic Product, depress the stock market, and cost millions of jobs.  Washington think tanks will busily grind out studies “proving” this.  My response would be to look at the city of Washington itself.  There is a height limit: no building can be taller than the Capitol.  This limit enhances the city’s beauty without in any way impoverishing its economy.  The same will be true when we put limits on other kinds of economic activity, especially if we recycle the commons scarcity rents equitably.  Markets and businesses and workers will do just fine.  More importantly, humans as a whole and other species will do much better.

Conclusion

My generation—the generation born in the mid-twentieth century—has had a grand party.  We have consumed more resources and created more environmental destruction than all previous generations combined.  We are leaving behind one horrendous mess for our children. But we haven’t departed quite yet. We still have time to leave a legacy.  The question I often ponder is, “What can my generation’s legacy be?”

The species we have exterminated can never be revived.  The harmful chemicals we have deposited in the biosphere cannot be removed in our lifetime.  The forests and wetlands we’ve destroyed will take a long time to heal.  I wish we could summon a Sorcerer who, with a wave of the hand, could put an instant end to the chaos we’ve unleashed.  Because that is not going to happen, the best legacy we can leave, it seems to me, is a blueprint for incorporating permanence and greater equality into our runaway economic system.

I think this can be done.  My remarks today are an attempt in that direction.  I think we have the ingenuity and the tools to do it.  The basic tools are familiar: property rights, trusts, limits, prices, and dividends.  We also have some time-tested principles to guide us: the riparian principle, the polluter-pays principle, the precautionary principle, and the centuries-old notion of the commons.  We can extend the principle of one person, one vote, to one person, one share.  We can redraw the boundaries between the commons and the market, and we can shift the divine right, in whole or in part, from private to common property.

It will, of course, take decades to build a strong common sector.  But at least we can see where we should be going and how we can get there from here—one step toward reverence for the commons at a time, one legal precedent at a time, one institution at a time.  I propose that we start now.

Question Period

I appreciate the creativity of your concept of building a counterforce to the market.  What I miss in your analysis is a closer look at the market per se.  I’m not suggesting that the market is in every instance a bad thing, but I would distinguish, for example, between the family farm and the corporate farm, as I believe E. F. Schumacher would.  I would also like to have you consider how much effort should be made toward a death penalty for corporate malfeasance—a corporate death penalty I mean, of course.

In California we have the “three strikes and you’re out” law, which applies to those who get caught smoking dope or the like, yet corporations with fifteen strikes against them are not out.  Obviously, that’s not fair.

I was involved for many years in efforts to head a socially responsible business and to generally try to make all businesses become more socially responsible.  I think those are worthy efforts, but I actually came to the conclusion that they are doomed to fail, or that they are not enough.  Yes, you can try to put the really bad corporations to death, but the commons will still be ravaged.  In other words, you need to do something that is external to the corporation.  I’m more or less willing to let corporations be corporations.  Yes, it would be nice to make them a little gentler, but what will make them gentler is to limit the harm they can do by having external limits.  It has to do with internalizing externalities; if they have to pay for pollution, they’re going to want to pay as little as possible.  The technology will shift from burning fossil fuels to clean renewable kinds of energy technologies just because corporations will respond to those incentives and those limits.

I often get into arguments with people who think we can reform corporations, and I certainly wouldn’t want to discourage anybody from trying, but I think the real solution is to build up the common sector.

Your reference to the grand party we’ve had makes me think you might have read Richard Heinberg’s recent book, The Party’s Over.  If you haven’t, I recommend it to you.

My concern is your reliance on the trust and the provision of a citizens’ dividend.  What I would prefer to do is sort out what ought to be public and what ought to be private.  I would like to see the elimination altogether of the income tax, which causes so much dishonesty and inefficiency and other problems and its replacement with scarcity rent, which we now know is easily upward of 30 per cent of Gross Domestic Product and perhaps as high as 40 per cent.  By collecting all that economic rent, we could provide the services for government that we reasonably ought to have and probably offer some kind of citizens’ dividend in addition.  To me that’s a far more efficient way to use the pricing mechanism to allocate resources.

I recognize the ideas of Henry George in what you say, and I’m very sympathetic to that.  At the same time, I’m thinking incrementally, and I wouldn’t want to abolish the income tax.  I’d like to make it more progressive for the foreseeable future.  And I certainly would not want to abolish the inheritance tax, which I think is critical.  In general, though, I like your idea.

I’m interested particularly in the creative commons, illustrated by the open sharing of ideas that you mentioned, and in the way the scientific discoveries and artistic expression of today stand on the shoulders of scientific and artistic endeavors of the past.  I’m concerned about the infringement on the intellectual commons of intellectual property such as copyrights, patents, and the jealous guarding of authorship.  How can we protect this aspect of the commons and collaborate more energetically as creative beings?

In my report there’s a discussion of that aspect of the commons; there wasn’t time to go into it in my talk.  The Constitution authorizes Congress to create patents and copyrights for limited terms.  The notion of the Founders was that authors would be given copyrights for fourteen years or some relatively short period of time, and then everything would enter the public domain.  You do want to have some way of rewarding artists and creators, but their work shouldn’t remain private indefinitely.

What’s happened, especially in the past twenty or thirty years, is that the copyrights have been extended again and again, and they are now essentially perpetual.  One of the key forces behind this was the Disney Corporation because it wanted to keep Mickey Mouse private forever.  Of course, Disney freely steals stories such as Snow White and Pinocchio from the commons, then privatizes them and copyrights them forever.  The same thing is happening with the Internet and with patents.  It’s an ominous trend, and I completely agree with you that we need to revive and strengthen the cultural and scientific commons.  I believe there’s a man in the audience, Lewis Hyde, who is writing a book on this very topic.

Thank you for your vision.  My question is about reverence.  The vision you presented is based on a shift in reverence from capital to the commons.  When I look at shopping malls and at the students I go to school with and at the larger world, I see such a deep reverence for and commitment to the market that I don’t see the shift happening.  How do we encourage that shift in reverence? Without it, can any of your vision come about?

Reverence is a matter of education and culture.  The shift is a slow process, but I do think it is underway.  Yes, it’s an uphill battle against huge forces: advertising budgets, shopping malls, all of that.  We need repetition of our message.  We need to have more people like Thomas Berry, and we need to promote his message.

I just wanted to point out that music has been returned to the commons in the past couple of years, thanks to Napster and much that has followed.  People can now pretty much get any music they want without copyright or any legal restrictions.  I’m wondering if a lot of other intellectual property may go that route, if technologies will simply liberate intellectual property from the commodity realm without us doing anything.

We do have to figure out a way to compensate artists, so it’s a tricky problem, but technology is certainly helping.

Concluding Remarks

I really don’t know how to add to what Andrew Kimbrell and Father Thomas Berry have so eloquently said.  What I’m thinking is how overwhelming it feels when we consider all the radical changes that need to be made and how seemingly little time there is to make them.  It’s depressing, it can be paralyzing, and my way of dealing with that is to say yes, we are up against this incredible juggernaut; yes, we have to change consciousness, we have to change law, we have to change economics, we have to change education, and on and on.  There is so much to be done.  We may or may not be able to make a difference, but we have to act as if we are going to make a difference.  We have to believe that we will, and it might just come about.  Change happens in surprising ways because it is nonlinear, and one day there may be a point at which it comes all at once.  There is no way we can foresee when or how, so it is crucial for us to act as if it is going to happen.